"Is not being,
then, unified number,
and beings number unfolded,
and Intellect number moving
in itself,
and the living creature number
embracing
everything?" (Plotinus)
This post argues for a Mathematical Neo-Platonism (MNP), where a transcendent source –
analogous to the One in historical Neo-Platonism (NP) – is seen as generating the Platonic reality of mathematics,
which in turn generates the physical universe in which we find ourselves. First I will discuss some interesting
parallels between NP and Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory (including the
axiom of Choice, together abbreviated as "ZFC"). Subsequently I will
discuss the consequences of Mathematical Monism (MM)
in light of the reduction of mathematics to ZFC. MM is the claim that all of
reality – including physical reality – consists entirely of mathematical
structures. According to physicists like Max Tegmark, MM follows from the
success of modern mathematical physics, since the latter describes physical
reality entirely in mathematical terms. I will argue that MM leads to MNP when
we take into account the reduction of math to ZFC, where the existence of the
empty set, designated by "∅", and a
small number of other axioms are sufficient to generate the entire universe of
pure sets in which the bulk of mathematics fits. Thus, given MM and the
reduction of math to ZFC, Leibniz's famous question "Why is there
something rather than nothing?" reduces to: Why does ∅ exist? And why
do the axioms of ZFC hold? As I will argue in my next post, it is only from a
Neo-Platonic perspective that these questions become fully answerable.
The analogy between set theory and Neo-Platonism
Is there any substance to MNP? Or is it no more than a pretentious sounding but
ultimately empty combination of words, a mere flatus vocis? Very interesting in this regard is the remarkable
role played by axiomatic set theory in contemporary mathematics. As most mathematicians
nowadays recognize, axiomatic set theory functions as the foundation for virtually all of mathematics – and some
mathematicians would go even further than this, e.g. John Mayberry: "set theory is not really, or not just, a foundation
for mathematics. It simply is modern
mathematics." (1988: 353) This privileged role played by axiomatic set
theory holds in particular for ZFC, which is standardly used in
mathematics and mathematical logic. As I will show in the following, ZFC
reproduces surprisingly many of the conceptual structures characteristic of NP,
notably its hierarchical universe deriving from a single and indeterminate
source. Now, suppose that this analogy between ZFC and NP holds up under closer
analysis. Wouldn't we then be justified in concluding that ZFC = MNP, since ZFC
reproduces NP in the context of mathematics? Let's see how far this analogy
goes.
As already noted, ZFC functions as the standardly used axiomatic foundation for
virtually all of mathematics. It is important to keep in mind just how
remarkable this intellectual achievement is! Especially when you realize that ZFC
requires only one existential axiom,
namely the existence ∅, and a small
number of other axioms stating which operations may be performed on sets in
general, in order to generate an endless "cumulative hierarchy" of
pure sets (i.e. sets containing nothing but sets), starting from ∅ as the hierarchy's sole existential basis. Amazingly,
virtually all of mathematics can be located somewhere in this hierarchy
(commonly called V). As the mathematician Enderton explains: "[M]athematical objects (such as numbers and
differentiable functions) can be defined to be certain sets. And the theorems
of mathematics (such as the fundamental theorem of calculus) then can be viewed
as statements about sets. Furthermore, these theorems will be provable from our
axioms [i.e. the axioms of ZFC, PS]. Hence our axioms provide a sufficient
collection of assumptions for the development of the whole of mathematics – a
remarkable fact." (1977: 11) Remarkable
indeed!
The hierarchical universes of NP and ZFC
To what extent does ZFC reproduce the core ideas of NP? As already noted, both
NP and ZFC present a hierarchically structured universe. Whereas ZFC gives us
the set-theoretical hierarchy V deriving from ∅, NP gives us
the metaphysical hierarchy One → Intellect → Soul → Nature (where
"→" stands
for emanation). And this analogy is all the more apt insofar as the Neo-Platonic
hierarchy is, like the set-theoretic hierarchy, a graded unfolding of
increasing multiplicity. For Plotinus, the One is an utterly undifferentiated
unity, which generates the plurality-in-unity of the Intellect, which in turn
produces the still more complex multitudes of Soul and Nature, finally
terminating in the utter chaos of unordered Matter. Likewise in ZFC, where the
hierarchy V starts on the 0th level (called "V0") with the utterly
simple unity of ∅, from there on generating ever higher levels of
complexity, such that V1={∅}, V2={∅, {∅}}, V3={∅, {∅}, {{∅}}, {∅, {∅}}}, and so on ad infinitum. Thus "in set theory
one is always climbing upward" (Devlin 1993: 47). And the higher one goes
in this endless hierarchy, the more complexity one encounters, until finally
sets are generated which are so mind-bogglingly huge that they escape
mathematical understanding altogether. True, the limit of what mathematicians
do understand about V is constantly being raised higher, thanks to continuing
mathematical research. However, since V is literally endless, it is clear that
some limit will always remain for us finite human beings: the limit may be
eternally moving upwards, but beyond it will always remain utterly
incomprehensible multiplicity. It is tempting to see this as analogous to the
way in which the Plotinian hierarchy ultimately dissipates in the
incomprehensibility of unordered Matter.
The 'empty unity' at the beginning
It is also at their starting points, however, that the set-theoretic hierarchy
V and the metaphysical hierarchy of NP are surprisingly similar. For NP, this
starting point is the utterly undifferentiated One. For V, this starting point
is ∅, the empty set. The analogy between them is obvious:
both ∅ and the
Plotinian One are, in a sense, 'empty unities'. Let's take a closer look at
this. Exactly why does Plotinus say that the One is an undifferentiated and
therefore 'empty' unity? This is actually a very complicated question, but for
now the simple answer must do. Plotinus reasons roughly as follows: if the One
were a definite something, i.e. if it had well-defined properties, then its
properties would in a sense limit its nature (since by having these properties
it would not have the contrary
properties), and thereby its power to produce would be limited as well, so it
would no longer be omnipotent. Thus, in order to be the cause of Everything,
the One itself must be (or rather: contain) Nothing. As Plotinus writes about
the One: "It is because there is nothing in it that all things come from
it." (Enneads, V.2.1.1-5) But,
as we have seen, in ZFC the starting point of V is likewise a kind of 'unified
nothing', namely, ∅, the set which
collects nothing. In a sense, then, ∅ could be seen
as the set-theoretic 'equivalent' of the Plotinian One. The crucial question is
obviously what this 'equivalence' is worth. Is it no more than a coincidental
analogy? Or does it rather reveal a substantial, doctrinal agreement between NP
and ZFC?
Before dealing with this question, however, it is interesting to note that this
analogy between ∅ and the
Plotinian One has been noted before, notably by Rudy Rucker in his widely read
book Infinity and the Mind. Rucker
(1995: 40) clearly refers to this analogy when he writes: "∅ is the One obtained by taking together...
nothing". Although Rucker does not mention Plotinus in this context, the
Neo-Platonic overtones of his mention of "the One" are loud and
clear. Also because Rucker (in the same section) explicitly states that he
inclines towards a Platonic interpretation of set theory (i.e. as describing an
ideal reality existing outside of space and time). So if the set-theoretic
universe (i.e. hierarchy V) constitutes a Platonic realm of ideal objects, then
Rucker's description of ∅ as "the
One" is clearly suggestive of a Neo-Platonic view, where ∅ is seen as a kind of transcendent, metaphysical
source of V, analogous to the Plotinian One. It would seem, then, that our
notion of MNP has already been anticipated by Rucker! Unfortunately, he does
not develop this suggestion any further, so at best Rucker remains a 'closet
Mathematical Neo-Platonist', hiding under the official cover of MP.
The Pythagorean element in NP
Let's return to the question how far the analogy between ∅ and the Plotinian One extends. Is this indeed a
substantial equivalence? One way to discuss this issue is by reversing the
approach taken so far. Up till now we have mainly focused on the question to
what extent ZFC repeats the core ideas of NP – but we can also turn this around
and ask: to what extent did NP anticipate ZFC? There has, after all, always
been a mathematical side to NP, partly because mathematics was already dear to
Plato himself (who saw in geometry a privileged way to understand the ideal
reality of the Forms), but mainly because the development of NP in the first
centuries CE coincided with a revival of interest in the mathematical
philosophy of Pythagoreanism. The philosophical and religious doctrines of the
historical Pythagoras are largely unknown, but the claim that "All is
number" was and is widely attributed to him. Thus Pythagoreanism has come
to be understood as a form of Mathematical Monism (MM), the claim that all of
reality consists of mathematics. However, together with this surprisingly
modern doctrine, Pythagoreanism always went hand in hand with ascetic and
magical practices, the latter based on a numerological belief in the magical
properties of certain numbers. This numerological side obviously conflicts with
the scientific aspect of Pythagoreanism. And this also holds for the
Neopythagorean revival of the first and second centuries which strongly
influenced the development of NP.
For the Neopythagoreans, reality consisted of a hierarchy flowing from God into
something they called the original Monad and then into the original Dyad and
finally into the numbers that shape physical reality. This scheme clearly
anticipated the Plotinian hierarchy of the One unfolding into the
multiplicities of Intellect, Soul and Nature (cf. Remes 2008: 15). In fact,
Plotinus was seen by some of his contemporaries (notably Longinus) as the
principal expositor of Pythagoras's doctrines (cf. Gatti 1996: 12-13). This
Pythagorean aspect of NP comes clearly to the fore in the very title of
Plotinus's master piece, the Enneads
(the 'Nines'), although it should be remembered that this title came not from
Plotinus himself but from his editor Porphyry. When Plotinus died in 270,
Porphyry took it upon himself to prepare the master's manuscripts for wider
circulation and by shifting around Plotinus's original texts (sometimes even
breaking them up into smaller sections), Porphyry obtained 54 treatises which
he divided into six groups of nine, "a combination of mystical numbers
that delighted him" (Wallis 1995: 46).
Given this Pythagorean side of NP (which grew even stronger in later
Neo-Platonists, notably Iamblichus), one could say that NP already was a form
of MNP right from the start. One could even say, with some goodwill, that the
Neo-Platonic hierarchy in its mathematical aspect – i.e. as an unfolding of
increasing multiplicity out of an original but empty unity – anticipated the set-theoretic hierarchy
of ZFC and other axiomatic set theories. In a sense, given NP's commitment to
the Pythagorean claim that "All is number", NP can even be said to
have anticipated MM – thus Plotinus, for example, writes: "Is not being,
then, unified number, and beings number unfolded, and Intellect number moving
in itself, and the living creature [i.e. the World Soul, PS] number embracing
everything?" (Enneads,
VI.6.4.29-31) But obviously the claim that NP anticipated ZFC and MM ultimately
runs afoul of the lack of scientific rigor and the intrusion of numerology into
the mathematical aspect of NP, which really did not go beyond vague claims
about the One generating the Dyad which in turn generates all numbers that
somehow "embrace everything". The how and why of this mathematical
unfolding of the One remained shrouded in mystery.
All in all, Plotinus and later Neo-Platonists really lacked the mathematical
theories that would have allowed them to precisify the Neopythagorean claim
that reality is a mathematical outflow from a single transcendent source. But
can't we now say that this situation has changed with the development of
axiomatic set theory in combination with the MM of modern, i.e. mathematical
physics? Doesn't ZFC+MM allow us to revive the Neoplatonic claim that reality
is a mathematical outflow of the One? If MM is true, then the reduction of
mathematics to ZFC implies that ∅ stands not
only at the origin of V but also at the origin of physical reality, because the
latter would then be a substructure of V. In short: MNP=ZFC+MM?
Modern physics and Mathematical Monism
So let's examine MM more closely. What exactly does it say? And is it
acceptable? To repeat, MM is the claim that all of reality – including physical
reality – is quite literally composed of mathematical objects. And, as already
said, although MM is of quite ancient origin, tracing back to the Pythagorean
claim that "All is number", it is nowadays making a comeback due to
the success of modern, mathematical physics. The basic point behind this
comeback is simple enough: since physics describes and explains the whole of
physical reality in essentially mathematical terms, the huge experimental
success of physics shows that the 'substance' of this reality is ultimately
nothing but what these mathematical terms refer to, namely, mathematical
objects such as numbers, vectors, functions, fields, topological spaces, etc. One
contemporary and very outspoken advocate of MM, the cosmologist Max Tegmark, summarizing
the main results from relativity theory and quantum mechanics, describes this
thoroughly mathematical nature of physical reality as follows:
"[W]e saw that the very fabric of our physical world, space itself, is a
purely mathematical object in the sense that its only intrinsic properties are
mathematical properties – numbers such as dimensionality, curvature and
topology. [W]e saw that all the "stuff" in our physical world is made
of elementary particles, which in turn are purely mathematical objects in the
sense that their only intrinsic properties are mathematical properties [...]
such as charge, spin and lepton number. [W]e saw that there's something that's
arguably even more fundamental than our three-dimensional space and the
particles within it: the wave function and the infinite-dimensional Hilbert
space where it lives [...] and the wave function and Hilbert space are purely
mathematical objects." (Tegmark 2014: 253-254)
It is on the basis of these considerations that Tegmark puts forward his own
version of MM, which he calls the "Mathematical Universe Hypothesis"
(MUH): "our external physical reality is a mathematical structure" (idem:
319). Similar arguments for MM can be found in scientists and philosophers like
John Wheeler, Frank Tipler, Roger Penrose, W.V.O. Quine, James Ladyman, Steve French, Don Ross, Vlatko Vedral, and
many, many others. I am inclined to agree with them that modern physics
shows MM to be true. However, I can't really argue for that claim here (other
than referring to the authority of said scientists and philosophers), simply
because of lack of space. So in the following I will simply assume that MM is
true, as shown by physics, and then develop the joint consequences of MM and
ZFC, to see if this leads anywhere in the direction of MNP.
Three remarks on Mathematical Monism
Before I continue, however, there are three remarks about MM that I would like
to make in order to put things in proper perspective. Firstly, it is important
to keep in mind that MM does not equate physical reality with the mathematical
realm in its entirety. That would simply be incorrect, because the vast
majority of topics studied by mathematicians have no connection to physics
whatsoever or to any other science apart from pure mathematics. Thus we have to
assume that if physical reality is a mathematical structure, then it is a relatively
small substructure of a much, much (perhaps infinitely) larger realm of
mathematical objects. True, it always remains possible that particular results
from pure mathematics find unexpected applications in physics (as happened, for
example, with non-Euclidean geometries which were first developed by pure mathematicians
but which turned out to find a surprising application in relativity theory).
But even if more and more of pure mathematics is 'sucked into' physics, it
seems extremely likely that pure mathematics will always dwarf the mathematics
needed for physics. This means that MM faces a particular obligation, namely,
to explain why certain substructures of mathematics and not others are singled
out as constituting physical reality, and exactly what this 'singling out'
amounts to.
Secondly, note that MM should be understood as a radicalized form of Mathematical
Platonism (MP). Both original Platonism and MP are dualistic in that they make
principled distinctions between the spatiotemporal realm of physical reality on
the one hand and the ideal realm of Forms / mathematical truths on the other.
MM, on the other hand, is monistic in
that it reduces all of reality,
including physical reality, to mathematics. In that way MM can be seen as a
radicalization of MP insofar as it takes the ideal realm of mathematics to
'engulf' the spatiotemporal realm. Tegmark puts this very clearly: "Mathematical
structures are eternal and unchanging: they don't exist in space and time –
rather space and time exist in (some of) them." (Tegmark 2014: 318) This
conception is also known in the context of special relativity as the "block
universe", where time is the fourth dimension of the geometrical structure
of spacetime, such that the entire universe, from past to future, exists 'at
once' as a single, mathematically structured 'block'.
My third remark is a caveat. Although I agree with the argument that the
success of modern physics shows that MM is true, I also think it is crucial to
note that this argument limits the truth of MM to physical reality, i.e. reality as described by physics. Thus there
might be non-physical realities that escape mathematical treatment. Indeed, I
think this follows from the famous Hard Problem of Consciousness, which shows
that the reduction of reality to mathematics stops short of how we experience reality, insofar as the
qualia of that experience refuse direct reduction to non-conscious building
blocks, be it the physical structures that form the human brain or the
mathematical structures that model the functional organization of the brain
(see Chalmers 1996). So here, in the Hard Problem of Consciousness, MM reaches
its limit. However, as I will argue in my next post, this fact – that
consciousness falls outside of mathematics – is precisely what will make a Neo-Platonic
approach to mathematics possible. For now, however, I will abstract from the
Hard Problem and simply assume that MM is true tout court. Why? Because this puts in very sharp relief the most
fundamental question of ontology...
Why does ∅ exist? Mathematical
Nihilism averted
If MM were true tout court, i.e. if all of reality reduces to mathematics,
then – given the reduction of mathematics to ZFC – Leibniz's famous question
"Why is there something rather than nothing?" would in turn reduce
to: Why does ∅ exist? And why
do the axioms of ZFC hold? Now it might be thought that this turns Leibniz's
question into a 'no-brainer' because – as is sometimes
said – "∅ is nothing". So to explain why physical reality
exists, we simply have to assume that 'in the beginning there was nothing' et voilà we have ∅, the sole existential assumption
needed to derive the whole of mathematics! But, obviously, this approach is nonsensical. First of all, ∅ is not nothing, it is rather
{nothing}, i.e. a set with nothing in it. And a set, even if it is empty, is
something, not nothing: "It is not the same thing as nothing because it
has whatever kind of existence a set has, although it is unlike all other
sets." (Gardner 1977: 15). This difference between ∅ and nothing is clarified by a
nice example from Enderton': "a man with an empty container is
better off than a man with nothing – at least he has the container". (Enderton
1977: 3) Secondly, even if we were warranted in simply assuming the existence
of ∅, we would still need to explain why the other axioms
of ZFC are valid, because it is only in combination with them that ∅ yields V. Clearly, then, we have to reject the idea
that ZFC provides an easy or otherwise attractive solution to Leibniz's
question because 'it starts from nothing'.
Nevertheless, this confusion of ∅ with some kind
of 'primordial nothingness' explains a lot of the current 'sexiness' of axiomatic set theory, as if the
latter were a sort of 'Mathematical Nihilism' giving new content and
credibility to the idea of an absolute creatio
ex nihilo. Such a view can be found, for example, in Jim Holt's popular
book Why does the world exist?.
Commenting on the set-theoretic construction of V on the basis of ∅, he writes: "Out of sheer nothingness, a remarkable profusion of
entities has come into being." Then, bringing in the hypothesis of MM,
i.e. that all of reality reduces to mathematics and thereby to set theory, he
writes: "The whole show of reality can be generated out of the empty set –
out of Nothing." (Holt 2013: 40) Admittedly, for Holt this is merely one
of the many possible solutions to Leibniz's question he examines in his book,
so we should perhaps not pin him down on it. The situation is different,
however, with the popular French philosopher Alain Badiou, who has developed a
wide-ranging set-theoretic ontology (including a political theory) based on a
conception of ∅ as a kind of "primordial
void" on which all existence is somehow founded, "the nothing
from which everything proceeds" (Badiou 2005: 59). Thus he writes: "In Set Theory, the
primitive name of Being is the void, the empty set. The whole hierarchy takes
root in it. In a certain sense, it alone "is"." (Badiou 2006:
98) As the scare quotes around "is" indicate, Badiou takes ∅ (the sole basis of existence, according to him) to be itself inexistent,
i.e. nothing. If this is the foundation of Badiou's ontology, then clearly that
ontology is based on a mistake.
Confusion of ∅ with 'nothing' widespread
This confusion is not just confined to foggy philosophers, however. It can also
be found in otherwise respectable set theorists and mathematicians, people
who really should know better. For example, Keith Devlin (1993: 36) in The Joy of Sets writes about the
construction of V: "we commence with nothing,
that is to say, the empty set". Mary Tiles (1989: 124) in The Philosophy of Set Theory writes that
the universe of sets "is a wholly abstract universe generated, as it were,
out of nothing" (admittedly, she qualifies her claim with the phrase
"as it were", but still, the damage has been done). John D. Barrow
(2000: 167), a prominent theoretical physicist and mathematician, writes about
set theory that "it has enabled us to create all of the numbers from
literally nothing, the set with no members". But the most curious case of
this confusion can be found in Enderton, whose remark about "a man with an
empty container" we quoted earlier precisely to dispel the confusion! For
if we look at the context of that remark, we see that Enderton himself is
confused as well. Here is what he writes:
"Note that {∅} ≠ ∅, because ∅ ∈ {∅} but ∅ ∉ ∅. The fact that
{∅} ≠ ∅ is reflected in the fact that
a man with an empty container is better off than a man with nothing – at
least he has the container." (Enderton 1977: 3)
Clearly, the notion of a container here represents the notion of a set, since a
set is a container of sorts (it 'contains' its members). So when Enderton
speaks of "an empty container" one naturally supposes he is referring
to ∅. But a closer look reveals that this is not the case.
Enderton in fact uses the difference between a man with an empty container and
a man with no container to clarify the difference between {∅} and ∅. So, in this analogy, {∅} is
represented by the empty container, whereas ∅ is represented
by no container at all! This clearly indicates that Enderton makes the mistake
of identifying ∅ with nothing. If {∅} is
represented by the empty container, a container with nothing in it, then this
means that ∅ is nothing. Similarly, if ∅ is represented
by a man with no container at all ("a man with nothing" as Enderton
writes), then this also means that ∅ is nothing. So even if Enderton has in his hands the
germ of the insight that ∅ ≠ nothing given his example of the difference between an empty container
and no container, he fails to see the true significance of this example.
Apparently, then, thinking about the empty set is a tricky affair and its
confusion with nothing is always lurking, even for the ablest expositors of set
theory.
Transition to MNP
So ∅ ≠ nothing. This means that Leibniz's question, even in its set-theoretic
form ("Why does ∅ exist? And why do the ZFC axioms hold?"), still
presents us with a genuine problem, i.e. a problem not solved by simply
assuming the 'existence of nothing' (whatever that is supposed to mean). As I
will argue in my next post, it is especially in the light of Leibniz's question
that the importance of NP will become apparent, because Plotinus was actually
the very first philosopher who grappled with this problem in a systematic way
and who developed a systematic answer in the form of his notion of the One as causa sui. So, if we return to our
analogy between ∅ and the
Plotinian One, and we allow ourselves to speak rather loosely, we could say
that Plotinus supplies us with a way to understand how ∅ has brought itself into existence! More about this in
my next post.
References
-Badiou, Alain (2005), Being
and Event. New York: Continuum.
-Badiou, Alain (2006), Briefings on
Existence: A Short Treatise on Transitory Ontology. Albany: SUNY Press.
-Barrow, John D. (2000), The Book of
Nothing. London: Jonathan Cape.
-Chalmers, David J. (1996), The Conscious
Mind: In Search of a Fundamental Theory. Oxford University Press: New York
and Oxford.
-Devlin, Keith (1993), The Joy of Sets:
Fundamentals of Contemporary Set Theory. New York: Springer.
-Enderton, Herbert B. (1977), Elements of Set
Theory. New York: Academic Press.
-Gardner, Martin (1977), Mathematical
Magic Show. London: Penguin.
-Gatti, M.L. (1996), "Plotinus: The Platonic Tradition and the
foundation of Neoplatonism", in: Lloyd P. Gerson (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Plotinus.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
-Holt,
Jim (2013), Why Does The World Exist? One
Man's Quest for the Big Answer. Profile Books: London.
-Mayberry, John (1988), "What are
numbers?", in: Philosophical Studies, 54 (3), 317-354.
-Remes, Pauliina (2008), Neoplatonism.
Stocksfield: Acumen.
-Rucker, Rudy (1995), Infinity and the
Mind: The Science and Philosophy of the Infinite. London: Penguin Books.
-Tegmark, Max (2014), Our Mathematical
Universe. New York: Alfred A. Knopf.
-Tiles, Mary (1989), The Philosophy of
Set Theory: An Historical Introduction to Cantor's Paradise. Mineola:
Dover.
-Wallis, R.T. (1995), Neoplatonism.
London: Gerald Duckworth & Co.
This statement is a gross exaggeration : "ZFC functions as the standardly used axiomatic foundation for virtually all of mathematics". A more correct statement would be "ZFC is the standard reference of a possible axiomatic foundation for virtually all of mathematics, as mentioned by usual mathematics textbooks passively copying each other". But over 99% of mathematical works make no explicit use of this particular formulation of set theory. In my site on the foundations of mathematics I present another axiomatic formulation of set theory which is much closer to the practical use of set theory in mathematics.
ReplyDelete